Sunday, February 24, 2019

Returning ISIS brides and the obligations of citizenship



Jeremy Au Yong  Foreign Editor,  FEB 24, 2019, The Straits Times

Was it right of UK to strip teen ISIS sympathiser of her citizenship?

While we are rather more used to discussing citizenship in terms of what a government owes to its citizens (a discussion often framed as a comparison to benefits which foreigners gain), the matter of what obligations a citizen might have, if any, tends to get less attention. I say "if any" because it is not immediately obvious that there are any, or that there is even a consensus on whether there should be.
Shamima Begum was just 15 when she - for reasons that only she can ever completely comprehend - stole her elder sister's passport, fled her east London family home and headed to Syria to join ISIS. Almost nothing was heard from her for four years until she was recently discovered in a refugee camp in north-eastern Syria, voicing a desire to return to what is ostensibly her home country. That desire, and the subsequent actions of the British government to strip her of citizenship last week, made Begum the poster child of the dilemma countries are facing as they contend with what to do with citizens who are returning from the Islamic State in Iraq and Syria (ISIS).

Begum is not the first ISIS sympathiser to try and flee, but with the terror group now a far cry from the organisation that once controlled a taxable population of some eight million, countries around the world are bracing themselves for the re-emergence of citizens who previously defected. The exact numbers are unclear but at least 40,000 fighters from more than 100 countries are thought to have gone to Syria to join ISIS when it declared a caliphate back in 2014.

With the dream of the caliphate now gone, many countries are expected to now deal with many trying to get back home. But that return is posing difficult questions about citizenship and the obligations both citizens have to their countries and vice versa.

Begum's story has resonated in part because it captures so much of the nuance of the issue. She doesn't fit any narrative about these fighters particularly well, yet there is enough about her to provide justification to nearly any argument one might want to make - the 19-year-old is something of a Rorschach test on returning ISIS brides.

For those convinced that the United Kingdom was right to deprive her of citizenship, Begum is a traitor, and a radicalised teen who married an ISIS fighter and has shown no remorse. In her interviews with British media, even as she was asking for sympathy, Begum never expressed any regret about joining the group.

"I feel a lot of people should have sympathy for me, for everything I've been through. You know, I didn't know what I was getting into when I left," she told Sky News.
She would even go on to argue that she did nothing wrong.

"When I went to Syria, I was just a housewife, the entire four years I stayed at home, took care of my husband, took care of my kids. I never did anything. I never made propaganda, I never encouraged people to come to Syria," she said.

For those who think the British government should not have revoked her citizenship, Begum is a misguided teen, now with a newborn, who can be treated with compassion without sacrificing security.

Tied intricately to this issue is a debate on citizenship and the obligations of citizens. While we are rather more used to discussing citizenship in terms of what a government owes to its citizens (a discussion often framed as a comparison to benefits which foreigners gain), the matter of what obligations a citizen might have, if any, tends to get less attention. I say "if any" because it is not immediately obvious that there are any, or that there is even a consensus on whether there should be.

Those against the idea of a conditional citizenship argue that it demeans the value of citizenship and is potentially cruel or, if not, unfair. At the heart of the cruelty argument is the despair inherent in being stateless. Someone with no citizenship is deprived of some basic citizenship rights, including many protections that countries confer upon their citizens. The unfairness argument, in turn, stems from laws enacted that have attempted to avert the statelessness problem. In some countries, only those who have dual citizenship can have their citizenship revoked, thus creating on paper a second class of citizenship that is less durable than the first.

Having citizenship with a catch can also diminish what it means to be a citizen. As Canadian law academic Audrey Macklin wrote in 2014 in a paper discussing laws in the UK and Canada on citizenship revocation: "Citizenship emerges as an enhanced form of conditional permanent residence, revocable through the exercise of executive discretion."

On the other side is the argument that citizenship should be revocable because it is an implicit contract. Unlike, say, being a member of a family, citizenship is not some passive status that imposes no preconditions. This side doesn't suggest that citizenship can be taken away willy-nilly, but that there should be extreme scenarios in which someone's right to be a citizen is nullified. After all, if even families can disown their members, surely a country can too.

There is also a history of governments either locking away deviant members for life or imposing capital punishment. Both are examples of government taking actions that deprive their citizens of their core rights.

If one accepts the idea of a conditional citizenship, then the question becomes what that condition is. In Begum's case, those who want to keep her out would argue that treason - giving comfort and aid to an entity at war with your own country - is a reasonable condition.

I find elements in the arguments of both sides persuasive.

Intuitively, citizenship should be something that comes with duties. This is not to suggest that the actions most frequently associated with good citizenry - obeying the laws, paying taxes, voting, doing national service (in Singapore's case) - need to be prerequisites for citizenship. (A Singapore male who doesn't pay taxes, doesn't do national service and doesn't vote is still a citizen - a citizen in jail but a citizen nonetheless.) It is not so onerous an imposition to expect citizens not to side with the enemy in a conflict - whether this means taking up arms or simply looking after its fighters.

At the same time, the idea of a government turning its back on a citizen in this scenario poses its own set of dilemmas, foremost of which is the question of who is supposed to deal with the individual. Begum does not just disappear because her citizenship has been revoked. She has to live somewhere. The UK, for all its problems, would apparently be equipped to take Begum back, prosecute her and then punish or rehabilitate her. To respond to her desire to return by denying she is one of your own comes off as trying to make her someone else's problem.

If thousands more cases are to come, involving dozens of countries, that will be quite a number of people who are supposed to be someone else's problem. The risk this could have in making worse a terrorism problem that the denationalisation was supposed to fix is significant.

And that seems to be the rub between the conflicting sides on the citizenship issue.

While there is more than sufficient justification for unmaking a citizen, it may not always be the right thing to do.



No comments:

Post a Comment